
By Stephen H. Watson
Why, and in what demeanour, did artist Paul Klee have any such major influence on twentieth-century thinkers? His paintings and his writing encouraged top philosophers to supply key texts in twentieth-century aesthetics, texts that encouraged next artwork heritage and criticism.
Heidegger, Adorno, Benjamin, Merleau-Ponty, Lyotard, Sartre, Foucault, Blanchot, Derrida, and Marion are one of the philosophers who've engaged with Klee's artwork and writings. Their perspectives are usually considered far away from one another, yet Watson places them in dialog. His element isn't really to vindicate any ultimate interpretation of Klee yet to permit his interpreters' diversified bills to have interaction, to make clear their and on Klee's paintings, and, in flip, to delineate either a background and a theoretical difficult of their midst. Crescent Moon over the Rational finds an evolving theoretical constellation of interpretations and their questions (theoretical, inventive, and political) that deal with and constantly renew Klee's wealthy legacies.
Read or Download Crescent Moon over the Rational: Philosophical Interpretations of Paul Klee PDF
Similar phenomenology books
Traditional and Analytical Philosophy: Lectures on the Philosophy of Language
An important research of a few of the crucial and abiding questions of metaphysics and the philosophy of language through essentially the most eminent modern German philosophers. initially released in 1976, it was once first translated into English in 1982. Ernst Tugendhat used to be educated within the Heideggerian modes of phenomenological and hermeneutical pondering.
Phantasy, Image Consciousness, and Memory (1898–1925)
This is often the 1st English translation of Husserliana XXIII, the amount within the severe version of Edmund Husserl's works that gathers jointly a wealthy array of posthumous texts on representational recognition. The lectures and sketches comprising this paintings make on hand the main profound and accomplished Husserlian account of snapshot realization.
Postmodern Philosophy and the Scientific Turn
What can come of a systematic engagement with postmodern philosophy? a few scientists have claimed that the social sciences and arts don't have anything to give a contribution, other than might be peripherally, to their study. Dorothea E. Olkowski exhibits that the ancient hyperlink among technology and philosophy, arithmetic itself, performs a primary function within the improvement of the worldviews that force either fields.
In Defense of Things: Archaeology and the Ontology of Objects
In a lot fresh pondering, social and cultural geographical regions are considered current previous to―or indifferent from―things, materiality, and panorama. it's always assumed, for instance, that issues are solely 'constructed' via social or cultural perceptions and feature no lifestyles in and of themselves. Bjornar Olsen takes a distinct place.
- Husserl and Heidegger on Reduction, Primordiality, and the Categorial: Phenomenology Beyond its Original Divide
- Supplements : from the earliest essays to Being and time and beyond
- The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy: Volume 6
- Ethics of Writing (SUNY Series in Contemporary Italian Philosophy)
- Impetus and Equipoise in the Life-Strategies of Reason: Logos and Life Book 4
- Intrigues: From Being to the Other
Extra info for Crescent Moon over the Rational: Philosophical Interpretations of Paul Klee
Example text
24 On the Withdrawal of the Beautiful truly articulate what Merleau-Ponty calls “the effort of modern painting,” which has been “directed not so much toward choosing between line and color, or even between the figuration of things and the creation of signs, as it has been toward multiplying systems of equivalences” (EM: 182). Klee’s search for the logos of the invisible in ascent, that is, a higher world, seems to conflict with Merleau-Ponty. For Merleau-Ponty, this transcendence emerges most primordially from below, first of all in the “profound latency” of the body, in our sensibility, the invisible’s reversibility or adherence to the visible, and the earth (EM: 187).
It is precisely this inherent movement that makes it figurative, giving the graphic line “the schematic fairy-tale quality of the imaginary” (N: 76). Hence originates Klee’s objections against the classical view of Lessing (and Hegel, we should add) that painting is a spatial and not a temporal art (N: 78). This view reduces painting to a matrix of dots rather than Klee’s conception by which it emerges, like nature itself, everywhere as movement and as genesis, the articulation of an inner realm antecedent to spatial stasis, an interplay of rhythms (N: 169).
41 Recourse to origins is no longer grounded in the substantive forms of the past but is itself productive and captures the productive transformation in abstraction. As Merleau-Ponty put it, “the originary is not of one sole type, it is not all behind us” (VI: 124). From the outset, Merleau-Ponty insisted on parsing formal truths not as a return to Platonist eternal ideas but rather as results of “productive imagination” (PhP: 386). He also distinguished his account from all naïve naturalist abstraction.